Skip to main content

Developing public health ethics learning modules – can we learn from critical pedagogy?

Abstract

Curriculum development in masters of public health programs that effectively meets the complex ethical challenges of the 21st century is an important part of public health education and requires ethical reasoning and purposively thinking. Current master programs in Public Health do not regularly include modules in public health ethics. The aim of this paper is to present background and theoretical foundation for developing a methodology and methods to develop public health ethics modules for curriculum development in public health programs. We describe ethical reasoning in medicine and in Public Health, specify pedagogical approaches and key assignments organized around the critical pedagogy.

Introduction

When asked to write a review on methodology to develop Public Health ethics modules we immediately thought among others about ethical challenges in the 21st century such as the commercial creation and sale of embryos, child abuse, domestic violence, elder abuse, wars and terrorism and health disparities. Are Public Health students prepared for these Public Health threats be traditional Public Health contents and traditional conventional pedagogy?

Much work has been done in the past two decades to develop theories of Public Health ethics [15]. However, a series of articles indicated that the teaching of ethics in Schools of Public Health is still relatively limited [6]. Only in some schools of Public Health in the United States (e.g. in the Harvard School of Public Health, the School of Public Health, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill), and the United Kingdom (e.g. at the London School for Hygiene and Tropical Medicine), ethics modules in Public Health are offered. This chapter recognizes that many countries have national qualifications frameworks for Public Health and that each institution has its own realities and needs. Yet, we will discuss a theoretical framework for developing Public Health ethics modules (contents and pedagogy).

Review

Paulo Freire and critical pedagogy theory

There are a variety of models for the design of modules in Bachelor, Master and PhD courses and many of the same issues are relevant in the context of designing ethics modules such as definition of aims, agreement on learning outcomes and resources, learning and teaching strategies, assessment criteria and evaluation. In the context of ethics modules in Public Health the tradition of critical pedagogy can take a prominent place.

The central idea of the critical pedagogy is a philosophy of education and social movement that combines education with critical theory. First described by Paulo Freire [7, 8], it has since been further developed by others such as Stage, Muller, Kinzie, and Simmons as a praxis oriented educational movement: “Education’s role is to challenge inequality and dominant myths…Learning is directed towards social change” [9]. As Freire argued, “Students, as they are increasingly posed with problems relating to themselves in the world and with the world, will feel increasingly challenged, and obliged to respond to that challenge…the resulting comprehension tends to be increasingly critical…Their response to the challenge evokes new challenges, followed by new understandings; and gradually the students come to regard themselves as committed” [10]. Freire viewed both research and education as venues where power operates.

This means that in the critical pedagogy approach the locus of the learning process is shifted from the teacher to the students utilizing learner-centered methods of enriching the educational content of teaching processes through joint decision making and collective learning. Thus, applying critical pedagogy in the development of Public health ethics modules can build on students’ knowledge, foster critical dialogue and analysis.

Ethical analysis in Public Health

In this section we outline major approaches to ethical analysis. Three approaches have shaped ethical reasoning in general, medical ethics and Public Health ethics. Ethical traditions have been shaped mainly by the deontological, consequentialist and virtue based approaches [1113]. Such traditions or paradigms have been extensively considered for the field of medical or clinical practice, but only comparatively recently have the significant differences and challenges within public health (with its collectivist focus on safeguarding the community and promoting well-being) been appreciated [14].

For Public Health ethics it is important first to come to some agreement of what is meant by public health. How it is defined and what is its content–mission, functions, and services? Definitions for health and for Public Health vary widely [15]. Health can be defined inter alia as absence of diseases, as well-being [16], or as the means to (or resources for, or foundations of) achieving goals [17]. Herewith, the point of Public Health is to protect and improve the health of populations and to engage social justice. Related to this focus on groups are the following definitions of public Health: “Public Health is what we, as a society, do collectively to assure the conditions of people to be healthy” [18] and “Public Health involves not only traditional government actions to protect the public from imminent danger, but also, at a more fundamental level, cooperative behavior and relationships of trust in communities, as well as a far reaching agenda to address complex social, behavioral and environmental conditions that affect health” [18].

In contrast to some other sciences more focused on creating new knowledge, Public Health practitioners know what they are hoping to achieve: the improvement in population health not in health of individuals [5, 19]. By public health ethics we mean understanding how to evaluate different courses of action and non-action and their individual and social consequences. As such, public health ethics embraces the range of methods used to analyze, interpret and evaluate the variety of ways individuals and groups interact with each other in a framework of ethics. Herewith, ethics refers to the way of evaluating, reflecting, understanding and criticizing what constitutes moral life and actions and manifests itself in reflections and case studies in Public Health [11]. Herewith development of modules in teaching public health ethics build on students’ knowledge to experience ethical modules as something they do, not as something done to them.

Generally, ethical reasoning seeks to provide an account of how humans assign and evaluate the rightness or wrongness of arguments and their consequences. Additionally, ethics is related to interpersonal duties and obligations that are not regulated or compelled by external authority. As indicated above, in the past (and sometimes still today) ethical reasoning in public health has been approached as a sub-set of medical ethics [14, 2022].

Following this application of ethical reasoning, it is necessary to distinguish between applied ethics and ethical theories in public health. Descriptive ethics relates to accounts of how humans behave, normative ethics considers what should be done. Both approaches have a long tradition in medical ethics.

Medical ethics in health care has a long tradition, and has focused on the dyadic clinical relationships between medical doctors and patients and a set of issues related to such relationships (e.g. autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, justice, consent, confidentiality [13]. The most common environment for such reasoning is the hospital where patients seek medical care. In those situations, the patient is in a vulnerable state, seeking relief from a problem. The clinician is in a role of authority which is based largely on their knowledge and their resources. Such, there is thus an imbalance of power between the patient and the clinician. This imbalance includes power imbalance in terms both of knowledge and power to act. The key principles of medical ethics are therefore related to such situation: regulating the potential abuses of power between clinicians and patients; between one who holds most of the authority and resources, and the other who is vulnerable in part because of his or her illness. Because of the orientation towards relationships in medical ethics, the concepts of autonomy and the’ negative rights’ of the person (e.g. the right not to be harmed) have tended to dominate in this field of medical ethics [23].

Taken together, traditional medical ethics has an occupation with distributive justice at the micro-level, to the neglect of broader social and global justice issues. In contrast, public health presents and creates distinctive ethical challenges, not just problems already familiar from medical ethics because it is embedded by definition in a population perspective [21, 2426]. As a consequence of the population perspective, public health sometimes promises benefits for population groups at the cost of benefits for individuals [24]. This may create tension between the rights and individuals and the rights and needs of populations [27].

Additionally, in contrast to clinical medicine which uses medical interventions to cure or treat existing illness, public health uses primarily non-medical means such as infrastructure improvement, policy, law and behavioral health to prevent illness. This aspect means that Public health ethics needs a broader framework to analyze competing interests.

Application of the critical pedagogy to development of ethics modules in Public Health

Several Public Health ethics frameworks have been developed, which were divided into practice–based, mostly deriving from several or no philosophical schools, and theory-based frameworks, mostly based on one philosophical school [15, 28]. Most notably, Beauchamp [11] Bayer’s New Ethics for the Public’s Health Beauchamp [2] and Childress’s Public Health Law and Ethics [29] were the first edited collections on the subject. Since then, however, there have been numerous books and scholarly articles on which scholars can now draw and Oxford Journals launched a journal called Public Health Ethics in 2008. We will briefly summarize approaches to teaching Public Health ethics.

First, deontological approaches in Public Health ethics, following Kant’s ‘categorical imperative’ argue that human beings ought to be treated with respect, as ends in themselves, not as means to another individual’s ends [25]. According to these deontological approach, ethical acts are appraised independently of the consequences that follow from them [28]. This ethical theory is closely aligned with accounts of human dignity and inherent worth. This is different in consequentialist theories [29]. In contrast, within consequentialist theories the rightness or wrongness of actions is looked at in terms of the consequences that results from these actions. For consequentialist, the rightness of an action is not intrinsic, but is determined by adding up the pleasure and pain it produced. The classical, widely used formulation of consequentialism is known as utilitarianism, where the best action is that which created the greatest good for the greatest number [30, 31]. Utilitarians are divided into subjective utilitarians and objective utilitarians. Subjective utilitarians believe that wellbeing is best defined by each individual’s personal experience, objective utilitarians want to centralize the assessment process. Utilitarianist approaches are prominent in Public Health ethics. These are often associated with economic analyses such as cost-benefit and cost-effectiveness analyses.

Rather than focusing on acts themselves or on consequences, virtue-based approaches in ethics examine the characteristics of actions of humans [30]. As such they identify qualities of behavior and focus on characteristics such as courage, humility, caring and wisdom [32]. Further approach is the Social justice bases approach. In this approach social justice itself is a virtue. However, as many of the values of Public Health are virtue based this approach has its own attraction for Public Health teaching at the moment. We can identify at least two applications of the virtue based approach: one view is that every community defines its own norms (relativist communitarianism), by contrast, universalist communitarians, believe in a single true form of good society and its associated virtues. [33, 34] Knowledge about these main approaches to ethics may serve to enhance self-reflection by students, and researchers and help them to be aware of existing guidelines and codes of conduct for public health [35].

The need for developing specific modules in Public Health ethics led to a meeting to form a Public Health Ethics Interest Group (PHEIG) in 2001. PHEIG had two main goals: the first was to develop a curriculum in Public Health ethics at the PhD level and the second was to host an international symposium on Public Health Ethics in 2002. In this symposium four key thematic areas were identified: surveillance and regulation, individual rights versus collective rights, risk and precaution and global health equity. However, in this symposium it became clear that there are further approaches within public health ethics (Table 1) which are useful for further development of Public health ethics [35].

Table 1 Goals of public health ethics modules

Additionally to the reasoning on approaches codes of ethic were developed. Codes of ethics are aspirational statements of expected qualities and behaviors of public health experts. In 2000, the graduating class of the Public Health Leadership Institute in the United States drafted a code for ethics as a group project, which is available at http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1447186/ [36]. This code is based on 12 ethical principles and 11 values and beliefs that underlie these principles. The consensus reached is seen in Table 2 [37].

Table 2 Principles of the ethical practice of public health

Principles in teaching public health ethics

One of the first issues students may need to confront is the problem of objectivity in Public health and the socially constructed nature of our understanding of public health threats. Similarly, whether a public health situation requires ethical attention, why and how, will be the result of competing perspectives. Ethics analysis accepts that Public Health science is value related and often power dominated. Real world examples in the form of case studies can contribute to generate critical thinking of students in Public Health ethics (See the article by Christopher Potter in this series). These case studies [38] may enable students to become critical subjects in the classroom and assume responsibility for the public health in the sense of the critical pedagogy: to communicate effectively, to act as advocates, to encourage and lead change, and to understand and balance competing needs and rights. This leads to a re-thinking of the challenge of power in public health. Many public health dilemmas are backed by power: power of those who define the ethical problem.

A commonly used definition of power comes from Max Weber, who defined power as the ability to influence others or events by force, rewards, favors and resources. Public health by definition is focused on populations, and on regulation and public policy. This adds to the peculiarity of public health ethics: the exercise of public authority and the imposition of public sanctions and penalties in an area as deeply personal as an individual’s health [1, 5]. As such access to power and how power is used means treating people as means lies at the heart of the development of Public Health ethics modules.

What is recognized as important for Public Health ethics and who defines the importance? Who defines what is important? Which possibilities are available to safeguard that individual people are not used as a means rather than an end–either as research participants or as research colleagues, or those who will be exposed to harm while safeguarding the wider population? These questions need further investigation and reasoning. One starting point for any public health practitioner analyzing the status quo or addressing a situation that appears to require change is to ask Qui bono? Who benefits? This simple question can begin to lay open the system that has brought about the situation, suggest ways of resolving it (including data collection and communication strategies), and provide a framework for assessing competing interpretations and suggested solutions.

Conclusions

Developing modules in ethics for Public Health with a critical pedagogy approach calls for faculty able to train in “real-world” applications of ethical dilemmas. Establishing ethics in Public health in situations of power, is a challenge. The theories outlined in this paper provide opportunities of ethical reasoning in public health by investigating threats to Public health in a human rights framework as regards content and methods.

References

  1. Thomas JC. An agenda for public health ethics. J Public Health Manag Pract. 2008;14(4):329–31.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  2. Bayer R, Gostin LO, Jennings B, Steinbock B. Public health ethics. Theory, policy, practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Coughlin SS. Model curricula in public health ethics. Am J Prev Med. 1996;12(4):247–51.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Viehbeck SM, Melnychuk R, McDougall CW, Greenwood H, Edwards NC. Population and public health ethics in Canada: a snapshot of current national initiatives and future issues. Can J Public Health. 2011;102(6):410–3.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Bayer R, Fairchild AL. The genesis of public health ethics. Bioethics. 2004;18(6):473–92.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Taylor HA. Incorporating ethics into teaching health policy analysis. In: Strech D, Hirschberg I, Marckmann G, editors. Ethics in public health and health policy: concepts, methods, case studies: Springer Netherlands. 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Freire P. Education for critical consciousness: Bloomsbury Academic. 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Freire P. Pedagogy of the oppressed: 30th anniversary edition: Bloomsbury Academic. 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Stage FK, Muller PA, Kinzie J, Education ECoH, Simmons A, Education AftSoH. Creating learning centered classrooms: what does learning theory have to say?: Graduate School of Education and Human Development, George Washington University. 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Freire P. Pedagogy of the city: Continuum. 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Beauchamp TL. Principles of ethics. J Dent Educ. 1985;49(4):214–8.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Faden RR, Kass NE, Goodman SN, Pronovost P, Tunis S, Beauchamp TL. An ethics framework for a learning health care system: a departure from traditional research ethics and clinical ethics. Hastings Cent Rep. 2013;Spec No:S16–27.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Beauchamp TL. Methods and principles in biomedical ethics. J Med Ethics. 2003;29(5):269–74.

    Article  PubMed Central  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  14. Dawson A, Jennings B. The place of solidarity in Public Health Ethics. Public Health Rev. 2012;34:65–79.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Lee LM. Public health ethics theory: review and path to convergence. J Law Med Ethics. 2012;40(1):85–98.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Calman KC, Downie RS. Ethical principles and ethical issues in Public Health. In: Detels R, McEwen R, Beaglehole R, Tanaka H, editors. Oxford textbook of Public Health. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. p. 387–99.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Seedhouse D. Health: the foundations for achievement. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons; 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Committee on Xenograft Transplantation: Ethical Issues and Public Policy. Xenotransplantation: science, ethics, and public policy. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press; 1996. 136 p.

  19. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics. 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press; 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Beauchamp TL. History and theory in “applied ethics”. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 2007;17(1):55–64.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  21. Callahan D, Jennings B. Ethics and public health: forging a strong relationship. Am J Public Health. 2002;92(2):169–76.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  22. Kass NE. Public health ethics: from foundations and frameworks to justice and global public health. J Law Med Ethics. 2004;32(2):232–42. 190.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  23. Coughlin SS. How many principles for public health ethics? Open Public Health J. 2008;1:8–16.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  24. Kass NE. An ethics framework for public health. Am J Public Health. 2001;91(11):1776–82.

    Article  PubMed Central  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Roberts MJ, Reich MR. Ethical analysis in public health. Lancet. 2002;359(9311):1055–9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  26. Schroder P. A separation of public health ethics from medical ethics. Bundesgesundheitsblatt Gesundheitsforschung Gesundheitsschutz. 2007;50(1):103–11.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  27. Horner JS. Medical ethics and the public health. Public Health. 1992;106(3):185–92.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  28. O’Neill O. Kantian ethics. In: Ashcroft RE, Dawson A, Draper H, McMillan J, editors. Principles of health care ethics: Wiley. 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Childress JF, Faden RR, Gaare RD, Gostin LO, Kahn J, Bonnie RJ, et al. Public health ethics: mapping the terrain. J Law Med Ethics. 2002;30(2):170–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  30. Petrini C. Theoretical models and operational frameworks in public health ethics. Int J Environ Res Public Health. 2010;7(1):189–202.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  31. Radoilska L. Public health ethics and liberalism. Public Health Ethics. 2009;2(2):135–45.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  32. Rogers WA. Virtue ethics and public health: a practice-based analysis. Monash Bioeth Rev. 2004;23(1):10–21.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  33. Anand S, Peter F, Sen AK. Public health, ethics, and equity: Oxford University Press. 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Dawson A. Theory and practice in Public Health ethics: a complex relationsship. In: Peckham S, Hann A, editors. Public health ethics and practice: The Policy Press. 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Committee on Xenograft Transplantation: Ethical Issues and Public Policy. Code of ethics for public health. Public Health Rep. 2001;116(3):270–1.

  36. Thomas JC, Sage M, Dillenberg J, Guillory VJ. A code of ethics for public health. Am J Public Health. 2002;92(7):1057–9.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  37. American Public Health Association. American public health association: public health code of ethics. Ig Sanita Pubbl. 2003;59(4):197–202.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Howard DE, Lothen-Kline C, Boekeloo BO. Using the case-study methodology to teach ethics to public health students. Health Promot Pract. 2004;5(2):151–9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jutta Lindert.

Additional information

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions

JL conceived the paper and wrote the first draft, CP contributed to the revisions and final manuscript. Both authors approved the final manuscript.

About the authors

Jutta Lindert holds a PhD in Medical Sciences. She is Professor of Public Health at University of Emden in Emden and at Brandeis University in the United States. She is president of the EUPHA Section on Public Mental Health. She is member of the ASPHER and ISEE Ethics Committee. Her area of expertise is Public Mental Health, neuropsychiatric epidemiology and applied ethics and bioethics.

Christopher Potter holds a PhD in Organization Behaviour and Analysis, and is a Fellow of the UK’s Faculty of Public Health. He teaches global Health policy on Cardiff University’s MPH programe and has held various public health director and health management posts in the NHS as well as having wide experience on overseas interventions in many countries. He has taught in a number of universities and is a member of APHEA’s Board of Accreditation.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lindert, J., Potter, C. Developing public health ethics learning modules – can we learn from critical pedagogy?. Public Health Rev 36, 7 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1186/s40985-015-0006-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s40985-015-0006-z

Keywords